Site icon Climate Etc.

On the role of trust in climate communication

by Judith Curry

Much has been written on the need for better communication of climate science and for rebuilding trust in the wake of Climategate. Such efforts are generally dismissed by climate skeptics as manipulative and further increase distrust.  But surely there must be better modes of communication between climate scientists and the lay public?

Jean Goodwin (featured in the previous post Manufacturing(?) consensus) has some interesting insights in this paper presented last January at the annual meeting of the American Meteorological Society.  I focus here on the abstract, which I find very informatively and concisely makes their argument.  There is also a link to a longer manuscript and the conference presentation.

Good reasons for trusting climate science communication

Jean Goodwin and M.F. Dahlstrom

Abstract. A recent analysis of poll results by the George Mason University Center for Climate Change Communication confirmed the expected: the controversy surrounding the CRU emails has resulted not only in a drop in belief in anthropogenic global warming, but also in a significant decline in trust in climate scientists. One main task confronting scientist-communicators must therefore be to renew citizens’ trust. Research in psychology and communication suggests that there are two general cognitive systems through which people reach judgments, and thus two broad routes to persuasion on this or other topics.

The first or “peripheral” cognitive system is characterized by the use of heuristics or rules of thumb; it is the basis of what is ordinarily considered intuition. This method for reaching judgments has of course some likelihood of going wrong, but at the same time is frugal, not expending scarce cognitive resources like time and attention. The second cognitive system, sometimes called “central” processing, is characterized by a higher degree of elaboration in reasoning, and involves what is normally considered critical thinking. Although it is effortful and slow, this method for reaching judgments is also likely to correct some of the errors of the easier peripheral processing.

JC comment:  This is a very important distinction, one of those “light bulb moments” in my understanding of the climate communication conundrum.

Much of the current literature on science communication focuses on techniques that affect an audience’s peripheral processing. For example, Matthew Nisbet and his collaborators advise communicators to carefully “frame” their messages in order to invoke some desired associations and experiences. Randy Olson’s recent Don’t Be Such A Scientist can also be read as a useful and amusing compendium of methods for increasing trust by appealing to an audience’s peripheral cognitive processes, projecting cues such as likeability, physical attractiveness, and dynamic delivery.

Appeals to peripheral cognitive processes, however, are unlikely to be completely successful in increasing trust in climate scientists. Some cognitive heuristics such as confirmation or “my side” bias will tend to further entrench the positions of those who already distrust scientists’ messages. Further, in a controversy as heated as that over global climate change, appeals to peripheral processing may be ineffective because when detected and called out by opponents, the communication techniques may appear manipulative and even fallacious. Not only will such messages be unpersuasive, they will tend to further increase distrust in the communicators.

JC comment:  It is exactly this kind of communication (peripheral processing) that the skeptics distrust and scoff at, essentially saying that improving this kind of communication increases the effectiveness of the “con job.”

In this paper, we therefore aim to supplement previous discussions of appeals to peripheral processing with a discussion of how climate scientists can give their audiences good reasons for trust, thus appealing to their audiences’ central processing/critical thinking. What are good reasons for trust? This has been the subject of significant recent scholarship in philosophy, political theory, and argumentation theory. These fields use humanistic methods such as conceptual analysis and pragmatic reconstruction to build theories of the kinds of reasons for trust which are likely to survive even harsh critical scrutiny. While social scientific methods can show us what heuristics audiences in fact are using–an empirical question–philosophical methods can show us what reasons audiences ought to accept as good–a normative or value question.

JC comment:  Appealing to central processing/critical thinking is exactly what I have been aiming for in my discussions on improving the public communication of climate science.  Without a clear distinction between the peripheral processing (or social packaging) of the communication and actual critical thinking, I have been frustrated in getting my points across.  I find this articulation of  peripheral processing versus central processing/critical thinking to be very insightful.

In particular, we will apply the line of research one of us (Goodwin) has developed in the communication subfield of argumentation theory, which provides an explanation of how trust can be secured even under conditions of deep disagreement. To summarize, this approach proposes that communicators can earn trust by openly taking responsibility for the possibility of errors and unforeseen consequences. A simple instance of this practical logic is the used car dealer who can reasonably be suspected of peddling lemons, but who succeeds in persuading some customers to buy by offering an extended guarantee. This enforceable undertaking of extra responsibility creates for his audience a new reason to trust him. As another example, this analysis suggests that the viewing public does not trust their local weathercaster because of his record of consistently accurate predictions. Instead, the public has reason to trust the weathercaster because they have repeated opportunities to observe how he takes the consequences for his mistakes.

When applied to the communication of climate science, this analysis suggests the somewhat paradoxical conclusion (also proposed in the work of Brian Wynne) that climate scientists may be more trusted if they present themselves as less certain.

JC comment:   Yes!!!

Instead of stressing the inerrant consensus that backs their statements, it would be a more effective appeal to gain trust via central processing if they openly made themselves vulnerable to criticism for any mistakes they may make. In order to make themselves vulnerable and thus earn trust, scientist-communicators will need to pursue two interlinked communication strategies. First, scientist-communicators will need strategies for assuring the public that scientists will in fact be held responsible and bear significant consequences, if it turns out that what they are saying is wrong. Second, because global climate change is not directly perceptible by ordinary means, scientist-communicators will need to develop and convey indicators which make future climate change visible to non-scientists in the same way that a car’s soundness or the local weather is visible. In sum, to earn the public’s trust in their risk communication, scientists must accept a risk themselves–the risk of being shown to be wrong.

JC comment:  This argument explains why the hockeystick controversy just won’t go away: it is the loss of trust of scientists that won’t given an inch in terms of acknowledging a mistake, particularly one pointed out by an “outsider” or skeptic.

JC conclusion: I’ll close with reproducing a paragraph from my building trust essay in the wake of Climategate:

The failure of the public and policy makers to understand the truth as presented by the IPCC is often blamed on difficulties of communicating such a complex topic to a relatively uneducated public that is referred to as “unscientific America” by Chris Mooney.  Efforts are made to “dumb down” the message and to frame the message to respond to issues that are salient to the audience.   People have heard the alarm, but they remain unconvinced because of a perceived political agenda and lack of trust of the message and the messengers. At the same time, there is a large group of educated and evidence driven people (e.g. the libertarians, people that read the technical skeptic blogs, not to mention policy makers) who want to understand the risk and uncertainties associated with climate change, without being told what kinds of policies they should be supporting. More effective communication strategies can be devised by recognizing that there are two groups with different levels of base knowledge about the topic.  But building trust through public communication on this topic requires that uncertainty be acknowledged.  My own experience in making public presentations about climate change has found that discussing the uncertainties increases the public trust in what scientists are trying to convey and doesn’t detract from the receptivity to understanding climate change risks (they distrust alarmism). Trust can also be rebuilt by  discussing broad choices rather than focusing on specific policies.

My building trust essay was lambasted by skeptics (see especially Willis Eschenbach).  With the passage of time, and notably with the interpretation provided by Goodwin and Dahlstrom, does my building trust essay now make more sense to skeptics?

Exit mobile version